=== === ============= ==== === === == == == == == === == == = == ==== === == == == == == == == = == == == == == == == == == ====
M U S I C T H E O R Y O N L I N E
A Publication of the Society for Music Theory Copyright (c) 1994 Society for Music Theory +-------------------------------------------------------------+ | Volume 0, Number 7 March, 1994 ISSN: 1067-3040 | +-------------------------------------------------------------+
All queries to: mto-editor@husc.harvard.edu +=+=+=+=+=+=+=+=+=+=+=+=+=+=+=+=+=+=+=+=+=+=+=+=+=+=+=+ AUTHOR: James Harley TITLE: Comment on Steven Smoliar's article KEYWORDS: Smoliar, computer music REFERENCE: mto.94.0.6.smoliar.art
James Harley Faculty of Music McGill University 555 Sherbrooke West Montreal, QC, CANADA H3A 1E3 jih@music.mcgill.ca
[1] I have been working in the area of "composition with computers" for some time now, so it was with interest that I read Steven Smoliar's article on the subject (1). I have not had a chance to see the publication that it originally appeared in (2), and therefore have perhaps read his work slightly out of context. Nonetheless, I think it is useful to comment upon a few of the issues which Smoliar raises.
[2] First of all, the abstract for this article makes general claims that are not substantiated in the body of the article. The rather ambitious opening, "this is an examination of the current state of the art in the computer composition of music," is fleshed out with a discussion of just one application, that of David Cope's EMI Project, with a passing reference to a single issue devoted to computer-generated music of the IEEE Computer Society *Computer* magazine. Cope's work is admirable, and certainly worthy of discussion, but we are here given no reasons as to why it is that his work "best characterizes the current state of the art." In fact, I would argue that his "recombinant" music is not "composition" at all, but "re-creation" or "style imitation," and hardly representative of original, creative work being done in the field, even by David Cope himself. In fact, there is an enormous range of work being done in the domain of "computer composition," from Ames and Barlow to Xenakis and Zicarelli. These composer-researchers are attempting to implement models of their own compositional "systems," such that the computer will be able to generate truly "contemporary music in a style which reflects the musical understanding or interests of the program designer (or, in certain cases, the user). Surely, in order to answer the question of "whether artificial intelligence has now solved the problem of turning a computer into a successful composer," one would have to look at the "creative" work being done, and not just the "re-combinant."
[3] Smoliar also raises the question as to whether the success of Cope's EMI system is due to Cope's own practical experience as a composer rather than its own "theoretical" knowledge (as he puts it, "just *who* is doing the composing[?]"). It may be useful to clarify the distinction between "theoretical" and "practical" knowledge here. There is an implication in this that the experienced composer knows how to obtain effective results in the concert hall without needing to be concerned with "theory." I think the real issue is whether one criticizes the computer program for not reflecting specific theoretical concerns or constructs, or whether one criticizes the musical output of the program for its musical-stylistic integrity. The criteria which Smoliar seems to use to judge the alleged computer-composer is the presence of "deep structure," as opposed to merely "surface structure." However, it is only possible to evaluate the work on this basis because it is "style imitation" rather than original work. Other aesthetic and theoretical issues must be articulated in order to judge the output of, say, Xenakis's computer program, just as they would be to judge one of his "non-computer" works. The real question here may be whether it would ever be possible to find "deep structure" in any "recombinant" music, computer-generated or otherwise, and whether that structure could be considered original rather than "borrowed." If the answer is yes, then the Cope-EMI results must be judged as having failed; if the answer is no, then Smoliar's evaluation procedure must be brought into question. In any case, I find it difficult to see how it can serve us in looking at other work in the field, especially given the difficulties others have had in applying such linguistically-based concepts of structure to non- tonal, or post-tonal music.
[4] I would also briefly like to take issue with Smoliar's claim that "whether or not music *has* a deep structure, much of our response, as individuals, is to surface features," and that it therefore follows that "audiences listen to *performances* rather than *compositions*." This is a bold statement, and is, unfortunately, unsupported in his article, apart, one assumes, from introspection as a result of attending live performances of EMI-generated music. Based on conclusions drawn from my own introspection, I am inclined to agree that the quality of a performance can be very convincing, whatever the "quality" of the music, particularly for the first hearing. It has been my experience, however, that repeated hearings of a piece (and for the sake of the argument, I am speaking only of live performances) tend to clarify the strengths and/or weaknesses of the music, and to build up an analytical-perceptual image of the music that would include something of the deep structure, if there is one. Therefore (and thank goodness!), it is still possible to distinguish (if not right away, then at least with time, given patience and good-will) music which "has come from a struggling genius, a commercial hack, chance decisions, or even a computer program," not to mention music by that irreducible entity, Mozart, from the would-be's and wanna-be's.
===================== 1. Smoliar, S. "Computers Compose Music, But Do We Listen." mto.94.0.6 (January 1994).
2. *Multimedia Modeling.* World Scientific. =====================
+=+=+=+=+=+=+=+=+=+=+=+=+=+=+=+=+=+=+=+=+=+=+=+=+=+=+=+
Copyright Statement [1] Music Theory Online (MTO) as a whole is Copyright (c) 1994, all rights reserved, by the Society for Music Theory, which is the owner of the journal. Copyrights for individual items published in (MTO) are held by their authors. Items appearing in MTO may be saved and stored in electronic or paper form, and may be shared among individuals for purposes of scholarly research or discussion, but may *not* be republished in any form, electronic or print, without prior, written permission from the author(s), and advance notification of the editors of MTO.
[2] Any redistributed form of items published in MTO must include the following information in a form appropriate to the medium in which the items are to appear:
This item appeared in Music Theory Online in [VOLUME #, ISSUE #] on [DAY/MONTH/YEAR]. It was authored by [FULL NAME, EMAIL ADDRESS], with whose written permission it is reprinted here.
[3] Libraries may archive issues of MTO in electronic or paper form for public access so long as each issue is stored in its entirety, and no access fee is charged. Exceptions to these requirements must be approved in writing by the editors of MTO, who will act in accordance with the decisions of the Society for Music Theory. +=+=+=+=+=+=+=+=+=+=+=+=+=+=+=+=+=+=+=+=+=+=+=+=+=+=+=+ END OF MTO ITEM